Monday, July 2, 2012

Fallacy of Equivocation


While there is wide disagreement among philosophers and logicians about a precise definition for the term fallacy,[1] it is generally agreed that fallacies are mistakes in reasoning that involve ambiguity and vagueness.[2] A fallacy can be a type of error in an argument, a type of error in reasoning (such as arguing, defining, and explaining), a false belief, or a rhetorical technique that causes any of these errors.[3] For present purposes, fallacy refers either to errors in the substance of arguments (as opposed to errors in the arguer’s thinking) or to the rhetorical tools that cause these errors. 

Fallacies are also described as being either formal or informal. Formal fallacies are concerned with highly technical errors in the logical structure of the argument.[4] Legal arguments rarely[5] contain formal fallacies.[6]

Informal fallacies are concerned not with the form but with the content (and possibly the intent) of the reasoning.[7] They are “proofs that appear at first glance to be sound but are fatally flawed in their reasoning or construction.”[8] And from a psychology perspective, “a fallacy is often defined as a mistake in reasoning used for deceptive purposes.”[9] While this certainly is not categorically true of all informal fallacies, “many of the informal fallacies are often used in the manipulation of opinion.”[10] Informal fallacies can also be difficult to identify. For instance, a slippery-slope argument often straddles the line between being persuasively plausible and fallaciously exaggerated.[11] For present purposes, a fallacious argument is either inductively very weak, or contains an unjustified premise, or ignores relevant, available evidence that the arguer should know about, and the argument can be used to persuade.[12] **

One such informal fallacy is the fallacy of equivocation: “the illegitimate switching of the meaning of a term during the reasoning.”[13] Below is an example of the fallacy of equivocation. Watch how the author uses the words majority and median:

Salary data show that the vast majority of lawyers earn rela­tively high salaries. According to the U.S. Census Bureau, lawyers boast the fourth highest median salary behind med­ical doctors, dentists and CEOs (some of whom have law de­grees). While the majority of occupations have median sala­ries between $20,000 and $49,999, the median for lawyers in 2010 was almost $113,000. Again, this was the median — the actual midpoint — which means the majority of lawyers made six-figures.


The problem here is that majority and median are equivocal words, or words that are subject to two or more interpretations and are usually used to mislead or confuse. The author equivocates because he uses the same words twice but changes the meaning of the words. Here is a breakdown showing the connotation of each phrase that uses majority or median.

Equivocal Words
§  vast majority of lawyers = most lawyers
§  majority of occupations = most occupations
§  median salaries = average salaries
§  median [salary] for lawyers = average salary
§  median = the actual midpoint salary with equal numbers of salaries that are higher and lower
§  majority of lawyers = a literal majority, or a number equaling more than half of the total (at least 50.1%)

The main, implicit conclusion that the author likely hoped his reader would draw might be something along these lines:

The vast majority of lawyers made at least $113,000 in 2010.

But this conclusion just doesn't follow from the premises. The more genuine argument leads to a different conclusion: a literal majority of lawyers earned a relatively high salary in 2010.

1.      Relatively high salary means more than $99,999.99
2.      Lawyers have the fourth-highest median salary
3.      Most occupations had a median salary between $20k and $50k in 2010
4.      Lawyers had a median salary of $113k in 2010
5.      Median is the midpoint on a range of salaries
6.      Only 50% of lawyers earned at least $113k in 2010
7.      But some lawyers also earned between $100k and $113k in 2010
8.      At least 50.1% of lawyers earned more than $99,999.99 in 2010; thus,

A literal majority of lawyers earned a relatively high salary in 2010.

Sketching out the argument in this way reveals its real weakness. Regardless of whether the argument actually commits the fallacy of equivocation, we should still reject its persuasiveness because the premises lead to an equally troubling conclusion:

1.      It is also true that 50% of lawyers earned less than $113k in 2010;
2.      And a proportionately large minority of lawyers earned less than $99,999.99; thus,

A large minority of lawyers did not earn a relatively high salary in 2010.



          **   These first three paragraphs come from a paper I published during my third-year of law school. Cory S. Clements, Comment, Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation: Using Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases to Win the War of Words, 2013 BYU L. Rev. 319, 331–33 & nn.61–72, available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2236669.
          [1].   The Internet is rich with information about the various types of logical fallacies. See Bradley Dowden, Fallacies, Internet Encyc. Phil., http://www.iep.utm.edu/fallacy (last updated Dec. 31, 2010) (content may also be accessed through an alternate domain, dewsberry.com, http://dewsberry.com/content/es/content/reference/fallacies/fallacies.htm); Charles Ess, Informal Fallacies, Drury.edu, http://www.drury.edu/ess/Logic/Informal/Overview.html (last visited Feb. 3, 2013); Logical Fallacies, http://www.logicalfallacies.info (last visited Feb. 3, 2013); Taxonomy of the Logical Fallacies, Fallacy Files, http://www.fallacyfiles.org/taxonomy.html (last visited Feb. 3, 2013).
          [2].   Dowden, supra note 1 (“The term ‘fallacy’ is not a precise term. One reason is that it is ambiguous.”).
          [3].   Id.
          [4].   Id. Formal fallacies are typically studied as part of a course on categorical, statement, and predicate logic. See generally Frances Howard-Snyder, Daniel Howard-Snyder & Ryan Wasserman, The Power of Logic (5th ed. 2012).
          [5].   Though rare, legal arguments containing formal fallacies do appear from time to time—even in judicial opinions. See, e.g., Cory S. Clements, Note, Judicial Takings in Vandevere v. Lloyd, 2012 BYU L. Rev. 423, 438–39 & n.117, available at http://lawreview.byu.edu/articles/1341676891_04clements.fin.pdf (construing Vandevere v. Lloyd, 644 F.3d 957, 966–67 (9th Cir. 2011)).
[T]he Ninth Circuit’s reasoning . . . is a non-sequitur. Logically speaking, the argument is invalid because it denies the antecedent, taking the following form: If (A), then (B). (Not-A). So, (not-B). To make sense of how the court’s reasoning is faulty, one must supply the implicit premises, (A) and (B), because the court’s argument made explicit only the contrapositives, (Not-A) and (Not-B). Thus, the argument with its implicit premises reads as follows:
If (A) Lucas’s remand order concerned the extent of the property interest, then (B) the extent of the property interest is not a matter of state law. (Not-A) Lucas’s remand order “did not concern the extent of the property interest.” So, (not-B) “the extent of the property interest” “is a matter of state law.”
Id. (footnote omitted) (“[T]he Court’s quarrel with the state supreme court did not concern the extent of the property interest in the beachfront land, which the Court’s remand order firmly suggests is a matter of state law but, rather, concerned the extent to which the state could invade a property interest without providing just compensation, which is a matter of federal law.” (quoting Vandevere, 644 F.3d at 964)).
For an in-depth explanation of how to recognize legal arguments that commit the fallacy of denying the antecedent, see Stephen M. Rice, Conventional Logic: Using the Logical Fallacy of Denying the Antecedent as a Litigation Tool, 79 Miss. L.J. 669, 683 (2010) (“[W]here the rules of logic are not observed, the argument takes the form of a fallacy. The Fallacy of Denying the Antecedent is one fallacy that results from failure to observe the logical rules. Where the argument denies the antecedent term of the hypothetical syllogism, it violates the rule that requires the antecedent term be affirmed. Accordingly, when the antecedent term is denied, the argument commits the Fallacy of Denying the Antecedent and is logically invalid.”).
          [6].   This is because formal fallacies are easier to spot than informal fallacies. E.g., Stephen M. Rice, Indiscernible Logic: Using the Logical Fallacies of the Illicit Major Term and the Illicit Minor Term as Litigation Tools, 47 Willamette L. Rev. 101, 107 (2010) (“These illogical arguments, called fallacies, can be identified by the pattern of an argument’s form, which makes them easy to identify, describe, and discredit.”). Judge Aldisert defines formal fallacy as follows:
A formal fallacy is any violation of any of the six rules of the categorical syllogism or the rules of the hypothetical or disjunctive -alternative syllogism. It is an argument whose conclusion could be false even if all its premises are true. It can be detected merely by examining the form (hence its name) or structure of the argument.
Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Judicial Process 141 (1976).          
          [7].   William F. Lawhead, The Philosophical Journey app. A-9 (3d ed. 2006) (stating that informal fallacies are “a type of bad reasoning that can only be detected by examining the content of the argument”).
          [8].   Roberto Aron et al., Trial Communication Skills § 1.12 (2d ed. 2011).
          [9].   Introduction to Logic: Informal Fallacies, P.L.E., http://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/fall acy_topics.html (last visited Nov. 14, 2012).
        [10].   Id.
        [11].   E.g., Mitchell F. Park, Comment, Defining One’s Own Concept of Existence and the Meaning of the Universe: The Presumption of Liberty in Lawrence v. Texas, 2006 BYU L. Rev. 837, 881 n.191 (“Suppose someone claims that a first step (in a chain of causes and effects, or a chain of reasoning) will probably lead to a second step that in turn will probably lead to another step and so on until a final step ends in trouble. If the likelihood of the trouble occurring is exaggerated, the slippery slope fallacy is committed.” (quoting Dowden, supra note 1)).
        [12].   Dowden, supra note 1.
        [13].   Id.

No comments:

Post a Comment